Word Gems
exploring self-realization, sacred personhood, and full humanity
Dr. Mortimer J. Adler's
Six Great Ideas
What is the basis of political rights?
|
return to 'Six Great Ideas' main-page
Editor's note:
Excerpts from Six Great Ideas are offered below, indented format; plus, at times, my own commentary.
|
How about the right to liberty, a good that is mentioned in
the Declaration as one of the principal goods to which we have
a right because it is indispensable to our pursuit of happiness
—to our living well?
To answer this question, let us first consider liberty of action
—the freedom, within limits, to do as we wish. Our natural
right to such freedom flows from our natural possession of a
free will and a power of free choice, which we exercise in mak-
ing the decisions that we must make, either rightly or wrongly,
in our pursuit of happiness.
What good would it do us to make decisions that we cannot
carry out? Without liberty of action, our freedom of choice
would be rendered totally ineffective. We would be exercising
it without achieving the ultimate good we are under an obliga-
tion to seek, if our freedom of choice is thwarted by unjust
limitations on our liberty of action, or is nullified by the depri-
vation of such freedom. Lacking free will and freedom of
choice, the lower animals have no rightful claim on liberty of
action. Zoos do not exist in violation of rights. However much
we may sympathize with caged or confined animals, we are not
moved by a sense of injustice done to them.
We feel differently about Epictetus in chains and Boethius in
prison. They could exercise their freedom of choice to will as
they ought and so they enjoyed the moral freedom that is the
prize of virtuous human beings. But virtuous human beings
are not always able to lead good human lives. Moral virtue
alone is not sufficient. Good fortune, in the form of beneficent
external circumstances, is also indispensable to the successful
pursuit of happiness.
Man's natural freedom of choice and his obligation to make
a good life for himself by making right choices is the basis of
his entitlement by natural right to liberty of action.
What about his entitlement to that variant of circumstantial
freedom that is political liberty?
The reasoning here runs parallel to that in which we have
just engaged. Again, human nature provides the answer. But
here, in place of man's natural freedom of choice as the basis of
the entitlement to liberty of action, is man's nature as a political
animal.
To be a political animal involves more than being the kind of
social animal that bees, ants, wasps, wolves, and other gregar-
ious organisms are. Social or gregarious animals need to live in
association with others of their kind. Man, too, is a social or
gregarious animal in this sense. He naturally needs to live in
association with other human beings in organized societies.
Unlike the organized societies of the social insects, which are
entirely determined by the instincts of the species, human so-
cieties are voluntarily formed and conventionally instituted.
They are natural societies only in the sense that man, being
gregarious, needs to live in association with other human
beings. They are at the same time conventional in the sense
that the shape they take—the forms of government, the laws,
the institutions, and other arrangements that constitute their
organization—are products of rational and free, not instinctive,
determination.
A political community is a society that is thus constituted. To
say that man is by nature a political as well as a social animal is
to say that he is by nature inclined to live in political commu-
nities and to participate in political activity—to be a self-
governing citizen in a republic.
In short, being political by nature means that man by nature
needs political liberty—the freedom of an enfranchised citizen
—in order to live humanly well. This is the basis of man's
entitlement, by natural right, to political liberty.
Deprived of political liberty, as slaves are or as are the sub-
jects of a despot no matter how benevolent, human beings can-
not fulfill all their natural propensities and lead fully human
lives. They are deprived of a real good to which they are by
nature entitled. The same is true of those who, living under
constitutional governments or in republics, are nevertheless
disfranchised and thus deprived of political liberty.
Are there any grounds to justify the disfranchisement of
human beings who are by nature political animals? Only two:
infancy and pathological disablement by amentia or dementia
—by a degree of feeblemindedness or of insanity that calls for
hospitalization and medical care.
In addition, criminal behavior justifies a deprivation of polit-
ical liberty, as well as liberty of action, either for a period of
time or for life. The criminal, by his own behavior, has himself
forfeited the exercise of a right that is unalienably his as a
human being. The exercise of that right, temporarily in abey-
ance, is restored in full measure when he has served his term,
if that is anything short of life.
|